Limits on performance are important because they provide clues about the nature
of the underlying processes.
--------
To explain this I have to step back and show you something interesting about
adults when they perform, and when they observe actions.
Performing actions (e.g. stacking blocks): you don't look at your hand but at
the block it will pick up, or, when holding a block, at the location where it will place a block.
That is, in acting the eyes move just ahead of the action.
--------
Flanagan \& Johansson (2003) showed that the same pattern occurs when adults observe another
acting.
In observing an action, the eyes move just ahead of the action.
This proactive gaze is important for our purposes because it can reveal goal-tracking ...
Flanagan \& Johansson (2003) showed that
‘patterns of eye–hand coordination are similar when performing and observing a block stacking task’.
--------
‘Positive relative times of the arrival of gaze at the goal area indicate that gaze precedes the agent’s arrival (predictive);
negative values indicate gaze arrival after agent arrival (non-predictive). Each age group is n = 12.
Error bars are s.e.m.’
GH : grasping hand; BH : back of hand; MC : mechanical claw
--------
Kanakogi \& Itakuar, 2011 show that abilities to grasp objects are correlated with
abilities to track the goal of a grasping action (as measured by proactive gaze).
x-axis is alpha, grasping angle. ‘An α angle value from 90 to 180° indicates that the infant
is engaged in a one-handed grasping action.’
‘The angle α is an index of the development of the onehanded grasping action and was
calculated by measuring the angle of a straight line de ned by the infant’s two hands (the
apex of the junction of the thumb and index nger) when crossed by an imaginary line
projecting frontally from the infant (Fig. 2b). If infants grasped for the objects with their
le hand, we reversed the red rightangled triangle from one side to the other side and
calculated the angle α in the same way. e angle α value of 90° corresponded to a perfect
alignment of the hands in a twohanded reach. erefore, the angle α value deviates from 90°
towards 180°, and bigger angle α value indicates more mature onehanded grasping. If the
angle α was over 90°, the infant was considered to be engaged in a onehanded grasping
action.’
--------
Further support for a link between action performance and goal tracking
comes from a developmental study by Ambrosini et al which studied whether proactive
gaze in infants is influenced by pre-shaping of the hand, and, in particular,
whether it is influenced by precision grips.
--------
By using no shaping (a fist), Ambrosini et al could treat sensitivity
to whole-hand grasp and precision grip separately.
--------
‘infants’ ability to perform specific grasping actions with fewer fingers directly predicted the degree with which they took advantage of the availability of corresponding pre-shape motor information in shifting their gaze towards the goal of others’ actions’ (Ambrosini et al., 2013, p. 6).
--------
Further, changing from a bodily action to the operation of a mechanical claw
(say) undermines the goal tracking effect.
So Kanakogi \& Itakuar, 2011 make two points:
(i) goal-tracking depends on action capabilities; and
(ii) only works for events involving biomechanically similar affectors
--------
Needham et al, 2002 showed that putting ‘sticky mittens’ on 3-month-old infants
(for 10-14 play sessions of 10 minutes each) resulted in their spending
more time visually and manually exporing novel objects.
--------
In this study, I think infants wore the mittens for just 200 seconds
(so the play sessions were much shorter than in Needhman et al, 2002).
--------
The observation was based on this study, which we saw earlier
--------
The results show that infants who played wearing the mittens first
were more attentive to the goal.
From at least three months of age, some of infants’ abilities to identify
the goals of actions they observe are linked to their abilities to perform
actions (Woodward, 2009).
But one potential objection to this study concerns observation vs performance.
The infants who played wearing sticky mittens first had spent longer observing
actions by the time it came to the violation of expectations trial.
Could it be observation of action (including one’s own) rather than performance
that matters?
--------
nb something gets stuck to the mittens; it's not really grasping!
--------
To address this issue, Sommerville et al. (2008) did a study in
which one group had observation while the other group had performance.
The participants were 10-month-old infants this time.
The materials were a bit different: so that training vs observation could
be as similar as possible with respect to the causal structure exposed,
there was a hook to get an object.
--------
The results show that infants with the training paid attention to the
distal goal (choice of toy) whereas those without paid attention to the
choice of cane.
--------
... or IMPAIR INDIRECTLY ...
Experiment 1 : shows that 6-month-old infants can distinguish a phonetic contrast
they have never heard before (one that occurs in Hindi but not their linguistic
environments.) (The contrast used was the Hindi dental /d/̪ versus retroflex /ɖ/
distinction.)
These graphs show a difference in mean looking time between cases in which phonemes
are alternated and cases in which they are not. (Iff infants distinguish, they should
find the alternating phonemes more interesting.)
Experiment 2: but not when they have a tongue-controlling dummy in their mouths
Experiment 3: but yes when they have a dummy which leaves the tongue free.
--------
I don’t think we have found strong evidence for this limit.
What we can conclude, more weakly, is that there is some limiting relation linking
goal-tracking and abilities to act.
--------
In infants (and adults),
goal-tracking is limited by their abilities to act.
Why is this true?
Why is goal-tracking in infants (and adult) limited by their abilities to act?
On the Simple View, goal tracking is a matter of thinking and reasoning about the
best means to perform an action.
On this View, there’s no obvious reason why
your goal-tracking should be limited by your abilities to act in this way.
Although I can’t jump over a house, I can perfectly well think about different ways
to do so and distinguish better and worse approaches, at least to some extent.